We're sunsetting PodQuest on 2025-07-28. Thank you for your support!
Export Podcast Subscriptions
cover of episode HoP 454 - By Appointment Only - Political Philosophy in the Second Scholastic

HoP 454 - By Appointment Only - Political Philosophy in the Second Scholastic

2024/10/13
logo of podcast History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps

History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps

AI Deep Dive AI Insights AI Chapters Transcript
People
P
Peter Adamson
Topics
Peter Adamson: 本期节目探讨了第二经院哲学,特别是伊比利亚半岛经院哲学家对政治权力的来源和合法性问题的思考。他们关注的核心概念是“dominium”(统治权),并非简单的统治或所有权,而是指对某物的合法控制。莫利纳认为,人类对其自身行为拥有自然统治权,但上帝才是人类身体的主宰。在国际法下,私有财产的引入使得人们可以对他们合法拥有的东西拥有统治权。动物没有权利,因为拥有权利和统治权的前提是能够运用理性。莫利纳将权利定义为积极的,而非消极的,即权利指向的是你控制的特定事物。政治统治权并非自然法的一部分,而是人类设立的产物,即使人类天生具有形成政治共同体的倾向。政治权威是人为的措施,因为人类的堕落导致了对法律的需求;政治权威必须遵守自然法,但允许不同的政府形式存在。政府的合法性取决于人民的同意,而非政府的类型;无论采用何种体制,目标都是相同的:人们服从国家权力是因为这样做是理性的。经院哲学家的政治理论与其因果论之间存在联系:国家的建立在某种意义上是自然的,因为人们有追求共同利益的自然愿望;但在另一种意义上,国家是人为的,是通过理性过程建立的。伊比利亚经院哲学家的理论为霍布斯铺平了道路,但他们的理解更为乐观:人们并非为了逃避自然状态的战争而接受政治统治,而是为了实现共同利益。对伊比利亚经院哲学家而言,政治生活是人类追求建立和繁荣共同体的理性表达和手段,而非权宜之计。经院哲学家认为婚姻在某种意义上是政治的,涉及正义关系;婚姻源于亚当和夏娃,即使没有罪恶,人类也会追求某种形式的共同体。经院哲学家对婚姻的论述中,女性的地位出奇地平等,尽管他们也认为妻子应该服从丈夫;共同体比生育在他们对婚姻的理解中更为核心。根据桑切斯的观点,婚姻并非天生永久的;基督教信仰中的婚姻永久性是效仿基督与教会之间不可破裂的联系,而非自然理性。苏亚雷斯认为,即使人类理性认识到国家对保障公共福利的必要性,人民仍然需要自愿决定建立国家。在苏亚雷斯的社会契约理论中,人民通过建立政治安排,创造了先前不存在的秩序和统一;只有在此之后,才能谈论“共同体”。苏亚雷斯理论中的社会契约似乎是虚构的,难以想象所有的人类在现代通讯技术出现之前就达成了任何默契。关于政治权威的来源存在一个先有鸡还是先有蛋的问题:共同体需要有权力才能形成统一的共同体,但只有在成为统一的共同体之后才能拥有和行使这种权力。维多利亚和莫利纳认为,人类天生就拥有对其自身(更具体地说,对自身身体和自由)的权威,并可以将这种权力转移给统治者;奴隶制是不自然的。苏亚雷斯试图调和人类天生拥有权威和政治统治只能通过自愿选择建立的观点。苏亚雷斯认为,权力最初存在于人民之中,但上帝的行动与人民的决定相结合,才能将一群个体转变为一个适当的政治联盟。萨拉斯批评苏亚雷斯的观点,认为如果个体的人民没有足够的权力来形成共同体,那么上帝必须增加必要的权力,这破坏了政治统治的自愿性和契约性。另一种对苏亚雷斯观点的解读是,自愿的同意行为能够创造新的权力,如同许诺或宣誓一样。在苏亚雷斯的观点中,所有的政治权威最初都是民主的,因为人民首先将自己构成一个拥有自治权的集体;理想情况下,他们不会保持民主,而是选择任命君主。苏亚雷斯的理论预示了霍布斯和其他早期现代社会契约理论家,但也具有其时代特征,体现了耶稣会精神。加入耶稣会类似于签订社会契约,成员自愿服从等级制度,追求共同利益和上帝的荣耀;同意理论也适合天主教知识分子。苏亚雷斯的政治哲学部分是为了反驳新教的观点,即他们的统治者是由上帝派遣来捍卫和传播宗教改革的;天主教坚持世俗统治者并非由上帝任命,而是由人民意志决定,这与教皇的权力形成对比。16世纪的宗教争论促进了重要的思想突破,一些思想的出现往往被错误地认为是在一个世纪或更久之后才出现的。

Deep Dive

Key Insights

What is the concept of dominium in the Iberian Scholastics' political philosophy?

Dominium refers to lawful control over something, where the dominus is the lawful controller. It applies to both personal actions and private property, which are governed by the law of nations.

How do the Iberian Scholastics define a right?

A right is defined as a capacity to do something, obtain something, or demand it. It is positively directed at something particular under one's control, not merely the absence of legal prohibition.

Why do humans need political authority according to the Iberian Scholastics?

Political authority is needed because humans are not perfectly good and require laws to ensure the common welfare. It is an artificial measure introduced due to the fall from grace.

What is the role of consent in the Iberian Scholastics' view of political authority?

Consent of the people is crucial for the legitimacy of a government, regardless of its form. It is through voluntary decision that people create an order and unity among themselves, forming a commonwealth.

How do the Iberian Scholastics compare their political theory to Hobbes' view?

While both acknowledge the need for political authority to escape a state of nature, the Scholastics view political life as a natural expression of human aspiration for community, unlike Hobbes' more pessimistic view of it as the lesser of two evils.

What is the role of marriage in the Iberian Scholastics' political philosophy?

Marriage is seen as a political alliance involving justice and mutual aid, reflecting the natural desire for community. It is considered a perfect society created through voluntary cooperation.

How does Suárez explain the origin of political authority?

Suárez suggests that authority resides originally in the people, who then voluntarily decide to form a commonwealth. Divine action cooperates with human decision to create a proper political union.

What is the significance of the social contract in Suárez's political theory?

The social contract represents the voluntary act of people coming together to form a commonwealth, creating the power to govern themselves, which they can then transfer to a sovereign or retain for democratic self-governance.

How does Suárez's political theory relate to the society of Jesuits?

Suárez's theory mirrors the structure of the Jesuit order, where individuals voluntarily choose to join and submit to an authoritative hierarchy, striving for the good of all and the glory of God.

Why did Catholic intellectuals embrace the consent theory of political authority?

Catholic intellectuals, like Suárez, emphasized the voluntary nature of political authority to distinguish it from the divine dispensation of the Pope's power, countering Protestant claims about the legitimacy of Catholic monarchs.

Chapters
This chapter explores the Iberian Scholastics' theories on political power, focusing on the concept of dominium and its connection to rights and ownership. It discusses the scholastic view of the origin of political authority, its relationship to natural law, and different forms of government.
  • Scholastics viewed dominium as lawful control, extending to actions and possessions.
  • Political dominion is artificial, arising from human decisions, not natural law.
  • Consent of the people, not government type, legitimizes rule.
  • Scholastic views on marriage highlight community over procreation, with surprisingly egalitarian aspects.

Shownotes Transcript

Translations:
中文

I'm Peter Adamson, and you're listening to the History of Philosophy podcast, brought to you with the support of the Philosophy Department at King's College London and the LMU in Munich, online at historyofphilosophy.net. Today's episode, by appointment only, Political Philosophy in the Second Scholastic. I closed the last episode by saying that there's a close connection between the Iberian Scholastic's theories of law and economics and their political philosophy.

That connection lies especially in the concept of dominium, which modern day scholars usually don't translate, perhaps because the cognate English word dominion and the literal translation lordship would both be too narrow in meaning. For the scholastics, you have dominium over something and are the dominus over it if it is lawfully under your control.

Thus, according to Molina, humans even have natural dominium over their own actions, though it is God who is the dominus of human bodies, which is why suicide is sinful. Once private property is introduced into human affairs, under the law of nations, people can have dominium over other things, namely whatever they legally own.

This is very close to, if not the same as, saying that people have a right to use the things they own. This is why I can't show up at your house without your permission, start eating your food and sleeping in your bed. When Goldilocks did that to the three bears, she was infringing on their rights because they had dominium over the house, the bowls of porridge, and the beds. Or at least she would have been if they weren't bears. Molina tells us that animals have no rights because having rights and dominium presupposes being able to use reason.

Molina defines a right as a capacity to do something, obtain something, or demand it, and relates this to the concept of ownership as follows. When we say that someone has a right to something, we do not mean that anything is owed to him, but that he has a power over it, and it would cause him injury to contravene that power.

Notice that he here defines rights positively, not negatively. In other words, a right is directed at something particular that is under your control. It isn't that by default you have a right to do or use whatever the law does not forbid. Molina's definition also suggests another close connection between dominium and power, since if you have a right to something, or dominium over it, then it is under your power. This brings us to what we're interested in for today's episode, namely political power.

In this context, translating dominium as lordship or dominion seems more natural. Like dominium over one's possessions, political dominion is not simply part of the natural law. All governments of whatever form exist only because humans have decided to set them up. Even if humans are, as Aristotle said, political animals and have a natural tendency to form into political communities.

Much as they decided to allow certain people to own certain things, they decided to appoint certain people to exercise authority over them. Also, as with private property, this is an artificial measure we need because of humans' fall from grace. Perfectly good people would not need laws, but would spontaneously do the right thing. Given that we are far from perfectly good, state authority is created to ensure that the common welfare is promoted insofar as is possible.

Just like anything else introduced through human law, political authority must never conflict with a natural law. But that leaves plenty of scope for different forms of government. Vitoria observes that a constitution does not need to be perfect in order to be legitimate. Unsurprisingly, the Iberian scholastics living under the kings and queens of Spain and Portugal praised monarchy as the most perfect form of rulership. But the Commonwealth can also decide to be ruled by an oligarchy or to rule itself as a democracy.

What counts is the consent of the people to a government, not the type of government they consent to. Whatever the constitutional mechanisms, the goal is always the same: people subject themselves to state power because it is rational to do so. Here we come back to another connection I've pointed out before, between the Scholastics' political theory and their theory of causes.

As you might remember, just two episodes ago, I finished off by saying that the creation of states is in a sense natural, because we have a "natural desire" to pursue the common good as a final end, final ends being one of the four types of cause in Aristotelianism. But in another sense, the state is artificial. It is brought into being through a rational process, whereby humans discern that they will be better off living under a government than living outside of all political organization.

This sounds a lot like Thomas Hobbes, who, not much later, will famously say that people submit to a sovereign to escape from the state of nature. It seems clear that the scholastics' theory did pave the way for Hobbes, but their way of understanding the situation is quite a bit more optimistic. It's not that there was a war of all against all going on, and to put an end to it, people accepted political rule out of pragmatic self-interest.

On the Hobbesian account, political life is the lesser of two evils. Accepting subjugation means that human lives are not quite as nasty, brutish, and short as they would be in the state of nature. For the Iberian scholastics, by contrast, humans are creatures who naturally want to form communities together, and see to it that those communities flourish. Political life is the rational expression of that aspiration and the means of its fulfillment.

We can see this in its most basic form by considering what the scholastics have to say about another kind of social alliance, one that involves substantially fewer people: marriage. Following Aristotle, the schoolmen saw this as being in a sense political, and even as involving relations of justice. Marriage goes right back to the first humans, Adam and Eve. Their conjugal union came before their fall from grace, showing that even without sin, humans would still pursue some form of community with one another.

The two spouses offer each other mutual aid and are seen as partners. This core idea means that scholastic treatises on the topic, like those by Vittoria, Tomás Sánchez, and Pedro Ledesma, give women a surprisingly equal status within marriage, even if they less surprisingly also think that wives should obey their husbands. For Ledesma, marriage is a perfect society, created and sustained through voluntary cooperation.

Along similar lines, Molina said that it is shameful if a husband has to resort to punishment to get his wife to do as he wishes. It's noteworthy that community is more central to this understanding of marriage than procreation. Of course, the scholastics do think that reproduction and child-rearing are important functions of marriage, but Sánchez explicitly says that a husband and wife may, without sin, have sex simply out of desire, and without intending to have children. Otherwise, why would we let infertile people get married?

Perhaps even more surprising is that for Sanchez, marriage is not by nature permanent. He knows that outside Christianity, divorce is common, so clearly it is not part of the natural law, or law of nations, that the marriage bond should be unbreakable. The fact that it is so in the Christian faith is simply an imitation of Christ's unbreakable bond to the church. In other words, the whole "until death do us part" thing is purely theological and has no basis in natural reason.

Thanks to romantic comedies, if not personal experience, we're all pretty familiar with the way that two people enter into the marriage bond. Two people fall in love, go out to dinner, one of them hides an engagement ring in the dessert, the other one swallows it by mistake, and so on. How, though, do we enter bonds of political union in the broader sense? Well, it depends which scholastic we ask. But since he's so frightfully clever, let's ask Francisco Suarez.

Last time, we saw him emphasizing that legal obligations can only arise through a voluntary act of will by a legislator, and that applies here too. Even if human reason is involved in grasping the need for a state to secure general welfare, there still needs to be a voluntary decision on the part of the people to bring the state into being. By entering into a political arrangement, the people create an order and unity amongst themselves that was previously absent.

In fact, it is only after this decision is made that we can speak of a "commonwealth" as opposed to a mere agglomeration of individuals, or rather of families, since by marrying and having children, people had already fashioned smaller units of social order before they created the state. This sort of theory is often described by philosophers as positing a "social contract" between the people who agree to submit to rule by a government.

As in other versions of that theory, Suarez gestures towards a supposed moment apparently shrouded in the mists of the distant past when a decision was in fact taken to unite into a commonwealth. This may seem rather fanciful, especially when it is invoked to justify the existence not of something as specific as, say, the Spanish monarchy, but the maximally general law of nations which prevails over the entire world.

As we saw last time, this early version of international law, too, was justified in terms of consent. But it's hard to imagine how all humans could have reached even a tacit agreement about anything, at least before the dawn of modern communications technology. Not that this technology has helped us to agree with each other now, either. I mean, it's not as if messengers were sent across the globe on horseback to check that everyone was happy to start letting people own private property.

Some philosophers of this period did try to put some historical meat on the bones of their contract theories. We saw this with François Haughtmann, whose Franco-Gallia looked back to Carolingian times to justify the constraints he wanted to place on the French monarchy. But when it comes to Suárez, a more abstract question comes to the fore. Let's just assume that people really did form themselves into a commonwealth and subordinate themselves to a system of rule. Where did they get the authority to do this?

It looks like there's a chicken and egg problem here. The community needs to have the authority, power, or right to make itself into a unified commonwealth, but it is only once it is a unified commonwealth that it can possess and exercise such power. Vittoria and Molina seem to say that humans just naturally have authority over themselves, more specifically over their own bodies and their liberty. They are created by God already having this power and are then able to transfer this power to the ruler.

This relates to something else we discussed last time. According to Vittoria and Molina, slavery is unnatural, or as we saw Molina putting it, "by natural right all are born free". It's then up to humans to decide what to do with that freedom, which is why one can, in extreme circumstances, sell oneself into slavery, and have that sale be legally binding.

It's also why under normal circumstances people may appoint a power to rule over them politically, not as a master over slaves, but as a leader over a commonwealth whose good is the leader's uppermost objective. Suarez seems to be torn between this sort of idea and the idea that political rule can only be instituted through an act of voluntary choice.

In favor of the idea that humans have authority over themselves from their very creation, he points out that the people must have a power in the first place before they can grant it to a king or other authority. After all, you can't give what you don't have. On the other hand, as we've already seen, he puts a lot of emphasis on the idea that the political commonwealth only comes into being through a contract among people who are going to be members of the commonwealth.

He solves this problem by suggesting that authority resides in the people originally, as if in the roots. But that God also needs to play a role. Divine action, in cooperation with the decision being made by the people, is needed to transform a group of individuals into a proper political union. I can't help noticing that this looks a lot like the Catholic position on grace, where good acts likewise result from a cooperation between God and human agents.

But another scholastic, Juan de Salas, did not find the solution so graceful. He thought that, faced with this chicken and egg problem, Suarez had resorted to pulling a rabbit out of a hat. If the people taken as individuals don't have sufficient authority to come together to form a commonwealth, then God must be adding the needed authority. But surely this undermines the voluntary and contractual nature of political rule, exactly what Suarez was trying to establish.

Salas argued that, to the contrary, the power of authority does reside naturally in humans. God is only involved insofar as he is the one who created human nature. If we were to imagine humans existing without God in the picture, then such humans could still appoint legitimate rulers for themselves. Another interpretation of Suarez's position, though, would help him avoid the charges made by Salas. On this reading, voluntary acts of consent just are capable of pulling rabbits out of hats or, if you prefer, making chickens without eggs.

We see this with the example of promising, or taking oaths. To take an oath is to create a new obligation that did not exist before. If I freely undertake to cook Goldilocks some porridge tomorrow morning so she doesn't have to go breaking into houses to have breakfast, then she can hold me to that promise. Similarly, when the people come together to form a commonwealth, they are creating the power to govern themselves, which they can then hand over to a sovereign, or retain for themselves if they choose a democratic form of government.

Actually, we can say that for Suárez, all political authority is originally democratic, because the first thing the people do is constitute themselves as a body with the right to self-govern. Ideally though, they will not remain a democracy, but decide to appoint a monarch. Because this is how monarchies first arise, the community is never under the obligation to accept tyrannical rule.

It would never be rational to enter into a contract that allowed for abusive treatment, so we can assume that people have never consented to such an arrangement. While Suarez's theory does anticipate Hobbes and other social contract theorists in the early modern period, it is also recognizably a product of its time. In fact, it's recognizably the product of a Jesuit. Suarez and his colleagues produced political theories that conceived the state as a much larger version of the society of Jesus.

You become a Jesuit by making a voluntary choice to join the Order, which is much like entering the social contract, since in so doing you submit to an authoritative hierarchy. Striving for the good of all, and ultimately, the glory of God, individual members humbly agreed to carry out whatever task their leaders assigned to them. In other ways, too, the consent theory was apt to be embraced by Catholic intellectuals,

This may surprise, because we've previously seen Protestants like Ockman pushing the idea that rulers need consent from their subjects in order to justify resistance to tyrannical rule, by which they meant tyranny exercised by Catholic monarchs. But as so often, this was a game both sides could play. Suarez may have devised his political philosophy in part to undermine Protestant claims that their own rulers were sent by God to defend and propagate the Reformation.

And, Catholics had an excellent reason to insist that secular rulers were not appointed by God but by the will of the people, namely that this would be a clear difference between those secular rulers and the Pope, who does wield his power by divine dispensation. Here then we're seeing, not for the first time, how the religious disputes of the 16th century encourage significant intellectual breakthroughs and the emergence of ideas that are often wrongly supposed to have emerged only a century or so later.

It may not be the last time we see that happen either, but we are slowly starting to edge towards the end of the current series. There are still a few figures I want to cover from Spain in this period. For one thing, having devoted so much attention to Shakespeare when covering Britain, it seems only fair to spend at least one episode on the greatest figure of Iberian literature in this period, Cervantes.

But first, I think it would not be quixotic to delve yet further into the thought of Francisco Suárez, perhaps the most impressive scholastic thinker we've covered since the medieval giants like Aquinas, Scotus, and Ockham.

Appropriately enough, for this purpose I am turning to an interview guest we last heard from back when I was covering those medieval figures, Tom Pink, who will be joining us next time for an interview that Goldilocks would enjoy, because it will consider Suarez's views on just rights. That's here on History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps.